Basil of Caesarea taught three divine Beings.

Summary

Basil of Caesarea was the first of the Cappadocian fathers and made a very important contribution to the development of Nicene theology.

In the Trinity doctrine, God is one Being with a single mind, existing as three Persons. It is often claimed that that is what Basil taught, but this article shows that Basil taught that the three Persons are three distinct Beings with three distinct minds.

That is also what the so-called Arians taught. However, while the Arians taught that the Son and Spirit are ontologically subordinate to the Father, what made Basil unique is that he believed that the Persons are ontologically the same. The Nicenes before Basil also believed that the Son is ontologically subordinate to the Father. They said that the Son is part of the Father, implying ontological subordination.

Although Basil taught that the Son and Spirit are ontologically equal to the Father (the same substance exactly), he preserved a certain order among the Persons. He refused to say that the Spirit is homoousios. He never described the Spirit as God, but described the Spirit as third in order and dignity. He believed that the Father alone exists without cause and maintained the priority of the Father.

This article elaborates on the following indications that Basil regarded the three Persons to be three distinct Beings:

1. Basil began as a Homoi-ousian, who believed in three distinct Beings. 

2. For Basil, homoousios meant that the Son’s substance is like the Father’s, implying distinct substances.

3. Basil said that homoousios corrects Sabellianism, for it keeps the Persons distinct.

4. For Basil, the Persons are instances of divinity just like people are instances of humanity.

5. Basil described the Father and Son as having distinct minds and wills, implying distinct Beings.

6. Since he maintained a hierarchy between the three Persons, it is difficult to imagine that Basil believed them to be one single Being.


Introduction

The Traditional Account

Due to research and a store of ancient documents that have become available over the last 100 years, scholars today conclude that the traditional account of the Arian Controversy – of how and why the church accepted the Trinity doctrine – is history written by the winner and fundamentally flawed.

The “conventional account of the Controversy, which stems originally from the version given of it by the victorious party, is now recognised by a large number of scholars to be a complete travesty” (Hanson).

“The diatribes of Gwatkin and of Harnack (published around the year 1900) can today be completely ignored” (Hanson, p. 95).

Books Quoted

Only a handful of full-scale books on the fourth-century Arian Controversy have been published since Gwatkin’s book at the beginning of the 20th century. This article series is based on books by world-class Trinitarian scholars of the last 50 years:

Hanson, R.P.C. (Bishop) – The Search for the Christian Doctrine of God – The Arian Controversy 318-381 (1987)

Williams, Rowan (Archbishop) – Arius, Heresy & Tradition, (2002/1987)

Ayres, Lewis (Professor of Catholic and Historical Theology) – Nicaea and its legacy, An Approach to Fourth-Century Trinitarian Theology (2004)

Anatolios, Khaled – Retrieving Nicaea (2011)

Basil of Caesarea

Basil became a bishop in 370. He made an important contribution to the development of the Trinity doctrine:

The three ‘Cappadocian theologians’, Basil of Caesarea, Gregory of Nazianzus, and Gregory of Nyssa “were together decisively influential in bringing about the final form of the doctrine of the Trinity” (Hanson, p. 676). Show More

Hypostasis and Ousia

Since these terms are important in this article, it is appropriate to begin with a brief overview of these terms:

The Trinity doctrine defines God as one Being (one ousia)  existing as three Persons (hypostases) (see here for a detailed discussion). In other words, it uses the terms ousia and hypostasis with opposing meanings.

In contrast, in the fourth-century Controversy, most people used the Greek words ousia and hypostasis as synonyms:

“For many people at the beginning of the fourth century the word hypostasis and the word ousia had pretty well the same meaning” (Hanson, p. 181).

Importantly, Athanasius, the paragon of the West, also used these terms as synonyms:

“Clearly for him hypostasis and ousia were still synonymous” (Hanson, 440). 

Both hypostasis and ousia meant an “individual existence” (Hanson, p. 193), “distinct existences” (Litfin), or “concrete individuals” (Anatolios, xiii). Show More

However, this article will show that, particularly following Basil of Caesarea, a distinction was later made between the meanings of the two terms.

Purpose

The purpose of this article is to show that Basil taught that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three distinct Beings with three distinct minds. This would be different from the Trinity doctrine, which defines the Father, Son, and Spirit as a single BeingBasil’s view may be compared to some other views during the fourth century:

Sabellianism

Sabellianism was still a strong force in the fourth century. The Sabellians believed that the Father, Son, and Spirit are a single Being with a single mind. The Sabellian minority at Nicaea supported the term homoousios and understood it to mean ‘one substance.’ In their view, the Son emerges from the Father merely as an energy. For example:

“Marcellus of Ancyra uses the language of ἐνέργεια (energy) to explain how it is that the Son can come forth and work without God being extended materially” (Ayres, p. 197). 

See here for a discussion of Sabellian theology.

Arianism

The Arians taught that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three distinct Beings with three distinct minds. For example:

Commenting on the Arian (Eastern) Dedication Creed of 341: “The bishops of Antioch … [were] insisting that Father, Son, and Spirit are three hypostaseis” (Anatolios, p. 24).

“Asterius (an early leading Eusebian) insists also that Father, Son, and Spirit are three hypostases” (Ayres, p. 54)

Since, at the time, the terms Being (ousia) and Person (hypostasis) were synonyms, when the Arians said “three hypostases,” they meant three Persons or Beings.

The Arians had accepted the term homoousios at Nicaea based on Emperor Constantine’s very vague explanation of the term. He said that it must not be interpreted literally, as if God is a substance, but that it only means that the Son is truly from the Father (see here). Show More

Nicenes

The Nicene theologians before the time of the Cappadocians, such as Alexander and Athanasius of Alexandria, like the Sabellians, understood the Father, Son, and Spirit to be a single Being with a single mind. They said that the Father, Son, and Spirit are a single hypostasis, meaning a single Person or Being. Show More

See here for a discussion of Nicene theology. The reader might expect to read here that the Nicenes said that God is one Being (one ousia) but three Persons (three hypostases). However, that concept did not yet exist. Alexander and Athanasius taught that the Father and Son are a single Person (hypostasis).


Ontological Equality

Basil was the first to teach ontological equality. 

When the Controversy began, all theologians regarded the Son as subordinate to the Father:

“With the exception of Athanasius virtually every theologian, East and West, accepted some form of subordinationism at least up to the year 355; subordinationism might indeed, until the denouement (end) of the controversy, have been described as accepted orthodoxy” (Hanson, p. xix).

Even Athanasius, the great defender of Nicaea, thought of the Son as subordinate in some ways. In the Nicene view, the Son is part of the Father, and, therefore, ontologically subordinate to the Father. Show More

Basil was the first to propose that the Father and Son are ontologically equal:

“In all the previous discussions (before Basil) of the term (homoousios) … a certain ontological subordination is at least implied” (Ayres, p. 206).

“In Basil, the Father’s sharing of his being involves the generation of one identical in substance and power” (Ayres, p. 207).

The next section will show that Basil, like the Eusebians (Arians), taught three hypostases. However, what made Basil different is that he believed that the Father, Son, and Spirit are “identical in substance and power.”


Three Distinct Beings

In Trinitarian theology, the three Persons are a single Being. Basil’s theology is often stated in ways that sound as if he also believed in only a single undivided substance (Being). But this section shows that he believed that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three distinct substances (three distinct Beings):

A Homoiousian

Basil began as a Homoi-ousian, who believed in three distinct Beings. 

Basil did not begin his career as a pro-Nicene. He began as an ‘Arian’; specifically, a Homoi-ousian, and gradually moved towards pro-Nicene theology:

“Basil emerged from a background, not of the strongly pro-Nicene theology of Athanasius, but of the school of Basil of Ancyra” (Hanson, p. 693).

“He came from what might be called an ‘Homoiousian’ background” (Hanson, p. 699)Show More

The Homoiousians were one of the Arian groups, and, as shown above, the Arians believed that the Son is a distinct divine Being. As a Homoi-ousian, Basil at first believed that the Son’s substance is similar to the Father’s, but different, which means that the Son is a distinct Being.

Homoousios

For Basil, homoousios meant that the Son’s substance is like the Father’s, implying distinct substances.  

Homoousios has two possible meanings. When two entities are said to be of the ‘same substance’ (homoousios), it can mean that they are a single substance or two distinct but identical substances. Show More

After Basil had moved away from the ‘similar substance’ formula of the Homoi-ousians, and had accepted the term homouousios, he continued to say that the Son’s substance is “like” the Father’s, implying two distinct substances:

Basil insists that “the Son, like the Father, is simple and uncompound” (Ayres, p. 204).

“He says that in his own view ‘like in respect of ousia’ (the slogan of the party of Basil of Ancyra) was an acceptable formula, provided that the word ‘unalterably’ was added to it, for then it would be equivalent to homoousios” (Hanson, p. 694) Show More

Basil said that homoousios corrects Sabellianism, for it keeps the Persons distinct. 

Basil wrote:

“This expression (homoousios) also corrects the fault of Sabellius for … (it keeps) … the Persons (prosopon) intact, for nothing is consubstantial with itself” (Hanson, pp. 694-5). (The Sabellians taught that the Father, Son, and Spirit are only one single Person.)

“Later, when he (Basil) had accepted homoousios as a proper term to apply to the Son, he still argued that it was preferable because it actually excluded identity of hypostases” (Hanson, p. 697).

Therefore, while Trinitarians understand homoousios as saying that the Father and Son are one substance, Basil explained it in a generic sense of two Beings (two distinct existences) with the same type of substance:

Adolf von Harnack “argued that Basil and all the Cappadocians interpreted homoousios only in a ‘generic’ sense … that unity of substance was turned into equality of substance” (Hanson, p. 696).

Basil remained a semi-homoiousian:

“Basil has moved away from but has not completely repudiated his origins” (Hanson, p. 694).

“Basil still seems to view the relationship between Father and Son in a fundamentally Homoiousian way” (Ayres, p. 190)

Hypostasis and Ousia

For Basil, the Persons are instances of divinity, just like people are instances of humanity. 

He regarded the Persons (hypostases) as particular concrete examples of a ‘generic’ Godhead (ousia), just like human beings are particular instances of a generic humanity. This is a clear indication that Basil thought of the Father and Son as distinct Beings:

Basil “discusses the idea that the distinction between the Godhead and the Persons is that between an abstract essence, such as humanity, and its concrete manifestations, such as man” (Hanson, p. 698). Show More

Therefore, Basil regarded human persons as appropriate examples of the divine Persons:

Basil assumed “that human persons are particularly appropriate examples” of “the nature of an individual divine person” (Ayres, pp. 207-8). 

“Basil discusses the individuation of Peter and Paul as analogous to the individuation of Father and Son” (Ayres, p. 207). 

Note that this also explains Basil’s understanding of the terms hypostasis and ousia.  Show More

Distinct Minds

Basil described the Father and Son as having distinct minds and wills, implying distinct Beings. 

“Basil … speaks of the Father choosing to work through the Son—not needing to. Similarly, the Son chooses to work through the Spirit, but does not need to” (Ayres, p. 208). 

“The Father, who creates by His sole will … the Son too wills” (Basil in De Spiritu Sancto). 

Basil said that the Son’s statements that he does the will of the Father “is not because He lacks deliberate purpose or power of initiation” but because “His own will is connected in indissoluble union with the Father.” Show More

Order among the Persons

Basil maintained a certain order among the Persons, implying the Persons are distinct Existences. 
“Father and Son are, indeed, the same in essence, but distinct at another level thus preserving a certain order among the persons” (Ayres, p. 195). 

For some unknown reason, he never described the Holy Spirit as homoousios with the Father and Son:

“Basil showed himself reluctant to apply homoousios to the Holy Spirit. … Homoousios was a word which applied particularly to the relation of the Son to the Father” (Hanson, p. 698). Show More

He also never described the Holy Spirit as God:

“While the Spirit is third in order and dignity, the Spirit is not third in an order of essences. Basil insists that the Spirit is to be accorded equal worship and honour with the Father and the Son, even if he is not willing to say directly that the Spirit is God in the same terms as Father and Son” (Ayres, p. 216). Show More

He referred to the Holy Spirit as third in rank:

“The Spirit is third in order and dignity” (Ayres, p. 216).

“The Spirit is third in order and even rank” (Hanson, p. 689). 

For Basil, the Father alone exists without cause. Since he teaches that Father and Son have the same substance, Basil was sensitive to the accusation that he could be accused of tritheism; three Ultimate Principles; three Beings who exist without cause and gave existence to all else:

“To speak of Father and Son as simply having the same ousia would be … to present him as logically another God” (Ayres, p. 190). 

To address this, Basil identified the Father alone as the ultimate Source:

“Let no one think that I am saying that there are “three ultimate principles … There is one ultimate principle of all existent things, creating through the Son and perfecting in the Spirit” (Hanson, p. 691). Show More

He maintained the priority of the Father:

“By the 370s Basil had evolved a formula stating that the activities of God all come from the Father, are worked in the Son, and are completed in the Spirit. In this formula Basil seems … to find a way to speak of the unity of divine action while still preserving the priority of the Father” (Ayres, p. 196).

Since Basil preserved a certain order among the Persons, refusing to say that the Spirit is homoousios and God, but describing the Spirit as third in order and dignity, and since he believed that the Father alone exists without cause, and maintained the priority of the Father, it is difficult to imagine that Basil believed that the Father, Son, and Spirit are a single existence.


Contemplation

Basil’s theology was not based on the Bible alone but on the Bible + ‘Contemplation’ (epinoia – ἐπίνοια). He explained epinoia as “concepts developed by the human mind” through “a process of reflection and abstraction.”

“For Basil, arguing that Father and Son are ‘unlike’ flies in the face of biblical material such as Col 1:15, Heb 1:3, and Phil 2:6.” As Basil read these texts, they “all … point to a community of essence between the generated and the one who has generated” (Ayres, p. 194). But how did Basil come to this conclusion? He answers:

“By ἐπίνοια [epinoia] we know that there is a unity of ousia between Father and Son” (Ayres, p. 194). 

Ayres explains epinoia as:

      • “Concepts developed by the human mind” (Ayres, p. 191-2),
      • “A process of reflection and abstraction” (Ayres, p. 192), and
      • “An intellectual contemplation of the reality of things” (Ayres, p. 193).

For Basil, we can only understand the Father, Son, and Spirit through “contemplation:”

Contemplation “throws away the letter and turns to the Lord” (Ayres, p. 219). 

“The contemplation of the Spirit necessary to understand the Spirit is itself at the core of Christian life” (Ayres, p. 219). 

That sort of contemplation is only available to “Christians who have attained ‘purity of heart’” (Ayres, p. 219). 

But Eunomius, Basil’s rival against whom he wrote three books, dismissed ἐπίνοια, as a way of gaining knowledge of God, as unreliable (Ayres, p. 191-2) and condemned it (Ayres, p. 193). He argued:

“If we know God only according to ἐπίνοια, then our knowledge is insignificant and our faith useless” (Ayres, p. 195).


Basil was a Philosopher.

It is traditional to accuse Arius of mixing the Bible with philosophy but the real culprits in this regard were the Cappadocians. Basil’s doctrine of God was based on pagan philosophy. Basil obtained the distinction between a common deity and the differentiation of Persons (as discussed above) not from the Bible but from pagan philosophy. The Cappadocians all relied on contemporary philosophy more than, for example, Athanasius and Hilary.

Influences

Ayres identifies “three basic influences on Basil’s account:”

“The first is Stoic terminologies about the relationship between general and individuated existence. … Stoics posited a universal … substrate (or ousia). … At the level of concrete existence individuals are also qualified by further qualities” (Ayres, p. 199-200). 

Secondly, “Neoplatonic-Aristotelian conceptions are used to interpret a basically Stoic scheme” (Ayres, p. 202). 

Thirdly, “we cannot, however, treat Basil’s distinction against a purely philosophical background. … It seems most likely that Basil’s evolution of the distinction occurred within a context where some such distinction was already clearly in the air” (Ayres, p. 202). 

The Cappadocians relied on philosophy:

Hanson concludes that “the Cappadocians all relied on the aid of contemporary philosophy more than … Athanasius and Hilary” (Hanson, p. 677). “A small work (by Basil) … at the end of Book V of Adversus Eunomium … is full of echoes of passages in Plotinus’ Enneads” (Hanson, p. 687)


Other Articles

The Meletian Schism – Athanasius vs. Basil of Caesarea

This article quotes mainly from world-class scholars of the last 50 years, specializing in the fourth-century Arian Controversy:

Hanson, Bishop RPC
The Search for the Christian Doctrine of God –

The Arian Controversy 318-381, 1988

Williams, Archbishop Rowan
Arius: Heresy and Tradition, 2002/1987

Ayres, Lewis
Nicaea and its legacy, 2004

Ayres is a Professor of Catholic and Historical Theology

Anatolios, Khaled,
Retrieving Nicaea, 2011

Summary

Eustathius of Antioch was a key driver for Nicene theology at Nicaea. However, since Eustathius taught that the Father and the Son are a single hypostasis (one single Person), he was exiled for Sabellianism soon after Nicaea. But his followers remained a significant group at Antioch.

Meletius was elected as bishop of Antioch in 361, but later accepted Cappadocian theology, in which the Son is a distinct hypostasis. The Cappadocians understood homoousios as meaning two distinct substances of exactly the same kind. 

The Eustathians were willing to say that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three prosōpa (masks or faces), but not three hypostases. The Cappadocian Basil of Caesarea objected that this is what Sabellius also taught.

While Meletius was bishop of Antioch, the Eustathians elected Paulinus as their rival bishop of Antioch. Like Eustathius, he was a Sabellian, believing that the Father and Son are a single hypostasis (Person).

Therefore, the Meletian Schism was a dispute in Antioch between two pro-Nicene groups:

Paulinus and the Eustathians were the traditional Nicenes. They accepted ‘homoousios’ as meaning ‘one substance,’ taught that the Father and Son are a single hypostasis (Person), and were supported by Athanasius and the bishop of Rome (Damasus). But Basil of Caesarea regarded this as Sabellianism.

The Meletians and the Cappadocians also accepted homoousios but understood it as meaning two substances that are alike in all respects. Therefore, they believed that the Son is a distinct hypostasis (Person). But the Western pro-Nicenes thought that this is Arianism.

Consequently, the two most important pro-Nicenes of the fourth century, Athanasius of Alexandria and Basil of Caesarea, found themselves on opposite sides in the Meletian Schism.

Eustathians

At Nicaea, Eustathius was a key driver for Nicene theology but was deposed for Sabellianism soon after

Antioch was an important center for Christianity in the 4th century. Eustathius, bishop of Antioch, attended the Nicene Council in 325 and significantly influenced the wording of the Nicene Creed. Constantine pressed for the inclusion of homoousios because Eustathius and his supporters favoured it. Show More

Eustathius taught that the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are a single hypostasis (one single Person). In his view, the Son or Logos is merely an aspect or part of the Father and does not have a distinct existence. Show More

For this reason, he was exiled for Sabellianism soon after Nicaea:

“It seems most likely that Eustathius was primarily deposed for the heresy of Sabellianism” (Hanson, p. 211). Show More

The Eustathians continued to teach that the Father and Son are a single hypostasis (Person). 

After Eustathius had been exiled, his followers remained a significant group at Antioch. They continued his teachings and elected rival bishops: 

“’One hypostasis’ of the Godhead was to become the slogan and rallying-cry of the continuing Eustathians” (Hanson, p. 213). 

Cappadocians

Meletius was elected as bishop of Antioch by Arians but later accepted Cappadocian theology. 

In 361, the Eusebians (Arians) majority elected Meletius as bishop of Antioch. However, Meletius later adopted the Cappadocian teaching, which accepted the Nicene Creed and the term homoousios. Show More

Meletius and the Cappadocians believed that the Son is a distinct hypostasis (Person)

“Basil (of Caesarea) had originally exhibited some discomfort with the Nicene homoousios as vulnerable to modalistic interpretations. His acceptance of this term was conditioned by his construction of an accompanying set of terminology to designate the threeness of God: Father, Son, and Spirit are each a distinct hypostasis, with a unique manner of subsistence (tropos hyparxeōs). Basil, a supporter of Melitius, pressed the followers of Paulinus to adopt the language of three hypostaseis in order to safeguard Nicene theology from a Sabellian interpretation” (Anatolios, p. 27).

See here for a discussion of Cappadocian theology.

The Eustathians said that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three prosōpa, but not three hypostases.

The Eustathians refused to say that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three hypostases. Instead, they said each is a distinct prosopon (pl. prosōpa). While prosopon can mean hypostasis, in Ancient Greek, prosopon originally designated one’s “face” or “mask.” In that sense, it was used in Greek theatre, since actors wore masks on stage to reveal their character and emotions to the audience. Applied to the Trinity, it can indicate different roles played by a single Person. For that reason, the Sabellians accepted the term, but Basil objected that this is what Sabellius also taught. Show More

Meletian Schism

While Meletius was bishop, the Eustathians elected Paulinus as their rival bishop. He was a Sabellian

Hanson describes Paulinus as “a Sabellian heretic” (Hanson’s Lecture). He was “Marcellan/Sabellian” (Hanson, p. 799). Show More

The Meletian Schism was a dispute in Antioch between two pro-Nicene groups. 

In the 360s-370s, there were three views represented in Antioch:

The Eusebians (Arians) rejected homoousios. 

The Eustathians were the traditional Nicenes. They accepted ‘homoousios’ (same substance) and understood it as meaning ‘one substance.’ They taught that the Father and Son are a single hypostasis (Person). Paulinus was their leader, and they were supported by Athanasius and the bishop of Rome (Damasus). But Basil of Caesarea regarded this as Sabellianism.

The Meletians (Cappadocians) also accepted homoousios but understood it as meaning two substances that are alike in all respects. Therefore, they believed that the Son is a distinct hypostasis (Person), and that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three hypostases (three distinct Persons). But the Western pro-Nicenes thought that this is Arianism.

The Eusebians (Arians), similar to the Meletians, believed in three hypostases. However, while the Eusebians regarded the Son as ontologically subordinate to the Father, the Cappadocians regarded the three hypostases as ontologically equal. Show More

Athanasius was a traditional pro-Nicene, believing that the Father and Son are a single Person

He believed that the Father and Son are a single hypostasis (Person). He condoned Sabellianism. For example, about the year 371, adherents of the Sabellian Marcellus approached Athanasius, presenting to him a statement of faith. Athanasius accepted it and gave them a document expressing his agreement with their doctrine. Therefore, he supported the Sabellian Paulinus. Show More

Athanasius and Basil of Caesarea were on opposite sides of the Meletian Schism. 

Consequently, in the 360s and 370s, the two most important pro-Nicenes of the fourth century, Athanasius of Alexandria and Basil of Caesarea, found themselves on opposite sides in the Meletian Schism. While Athanasius supported Paulinus and the Eustathians in Antioch, Basil supported Meletius and regarded Athanasius and the Western ‘one hypostasis’ theology as Sabellianism:

“The opening of the year 375 saw the ironical situation in which the Pope, Damasus, and the archbishop of Alexandria, Peter, were supporting Paulinus of Antioch, a Sabellian heretic, and Vitalis, an Apollinarian heretic, against Basil of Caesarea, the champion of Nicene orthodoxy in the East, later to be acknowledged universally as a great Doctor of the Church” (Hanson’s Lecture). Show More

Basil of Caesarea suspected Athanasius and the Western support of ‘one hypostasis’ theology as Sabellianism, with Marcellus as its main representative. Show More

Peter and Damasus, the bishops of Alexandria and Rome, also opposed Basil. 

After Athanasius died in 373, his successor Peter continued to support Paulinus and persuaded Damasus, the bishop of Rome, to do the same. Peter poisoned the mind of Damasus against Basil and Meletius. Show More

The Core Issue

The issue, whether the Son is a distinct Person, was the core issue of the entire Arian Controversy. 

The main issue in the Meletian Schism was whether the Son is a distinct Person. While Athanasius and the Eustathians said that the Father and Son are a single Person, Basil and the Meletians maintained that the Son is a distinct Person. Show More

This dispute between one and three hypostases in Antioch was also the Core Issue of the entire Arian Controversy. That difference explains all other differences between theologians:

If they are a single Existence (one hypostasis), as the Nicenes claimed, then the Son is eternal and of the same substance as the Father, and only one Logos exists.

But if they are two distinct Existences (two hypostases), then:

        • The Father alone exists without a cause.
        • The Son did not always exist but is a ‘creature, produced by the Father’s will.
        • The Son does not fully understand the Father.

See here for a discussion of the core issue in the Controversy. That article identifies the core issue by analysing the various phases of the Controversy and by showing who opposed whom.

If the Son is not a distinct Person, as Athanasius claimed, He cannot become incarnated. (See here for a discussion.)

Melitian Controversy

The Meletian Schism must not be confused with the Melitian Controversy. 

In the Melitian Controversy, several decades earlier in Egypt, Athanasius persecuted the Melitian Christians in his see:

“It seems clear also that Athanasius’ first efforts at gangsterism in his diocese had nothing to do with difference of opinion on the subject of the Arian Controversy, but were directed against the Melitians” (Hanson, p. 254). Show More

TABLE OF CONTENTS