Introduction
Purpose
The 4th-century Arian Controversy began with a dispute between Arius, a presbyter, and his bishop, Alexander of Alexandria, Egypt. Their disagreement escalated until Emperor Constantine called a council at Nicaea in 325, where Arius’ theology was presented, discussed, and rejected.
This article compares Arius’ theology with the views of the church fathers of the first three centuries.
Authors Quoted
This article series is based mainly on the following books, published over the past 50 years:
Hanson, R.P.C. – The Search for the Christian Doctrine of God – The Arian Controversy 318-381 (1987)
Williams, Rowan – Arius, Heresy & Tradition, (2002/1987)
Ayres, Lewis – Nicaea and its legacy, An Approach to Fourth-Century Trinitarian Theology (2004)
Anatolios, Khaled – Retrieving Nicaea (2011) |
The First Three Centuries
It is often thought that there was general agreement among the pre-Nicene church fathers. However, there was also significant disagreement, as the following high-level overview shows:
Logos-theology
Beginning with Justin Martyr, Logos-theology dominated the Gentile church. Based mainly on Greek philosophy, it taught that the Son (the Logos) always existed as an aspect of God but later became a distinct Person (a hypostasis), subordinate to the high God, as an intermediary between the high God and the physical creation. Logos-theologians, therefore, believed that the Son is a distinct divine Person. This remained the dominant view into the 4th century. Show More
“Ever since the work of Justin Martyr, Christian theologians had tended to use the identification of the pre-existent Son with some similar concept in contemporary Middle Platonism as a convenient philosophical device” (Hanson, p 22-23).
“The Son or Logos was eternally within the being of the Father, he only became distinct or prolated or borne forth at a particular point for the purposes of creation, revelation and redemption” (Hanson, p. 872).
“The theological structure provided by the Apologists lasted as the main, widely-accepted, one might almost say traditional framework for a Christian doctrine of God well into the fourth century” (Hanson). |
Monarchianism
Monarchianism, also called Modalism, opposed Logos-theology. They objected that Logos-theology violated Biblical monotheism with an unbiblical division of God’s substance. While Logos-theology believed in two divine Persons, the Monarchians maintained that only one divine Person exists and that ‘Father’ and ‘Son’ are two names for the same Person. They denied that the Son has any identifiable distinct existence. It follows that the Father died on the Cross. Show More
“This ‘monarchian’ view was an attempt to retain a strict type of monotheism for the Christian faith. It accomplished this goal by suggesting the Father and Son were different expressions of the same being, without any personal distinctions between them. In other words, the Father is himself the Son, and therefore experiences the Son’s human frailties” (Litfin).
“By their opponents they are accused of teaching that the Son and the Spirit do not have real independent existence and are in fact simply modes of the Father’s being” (Ayres, p. 68). |
Tertullian
In the 3rd century, Tertullian, also a Logos-theologian, attempted to address the Monarchian objections by teaching that God is a single substance and that the Son is a portion of the whole. In this way, he satisfied the demands for both monotheism and the distinct existence of the Son. However, as a Logos theologian, he taught that the Father was not always Father, that there was a time when the Son was not, and that the Son is subordinate to the Father, views for which Arius was later criticized. Show More
Tertullian wrote: “For the Father is the entire substance, but the Son is a derivation and portion of the whole” (Against Praxeas, Chapter 9).
“Tertullian believed … (that) God, while not ceasing to be what he always was, nonetheless extended himself or projected himself forward, so that the three Persons became more clearly distinguished. By means of these now-more-distinct Persons, the one God creates the world, rules over it, and enters into it for salvation” (Bryan Litfin).
“Tertullian … believed and taught that, though the Son or Logos was eternally within the being of the Father, he only became distinct … at a particular point for the purposes of creation, revelation and redemption” (Hanson, p. 872).
“For Tertullian, the Son is second in order” (Ayres, pp. 73-74).
(See here for a discussion of Tertullian.) |
Origen
Also in the 3rd century, Origen, the most influential author of the first three centuries, taught that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three distinct divine Persons (three hypostases), with the Son and the Spirit subordinate to the Father. (The Greek word hypostasis was the most important term in the Controversy, and meant a distinct existence.) Show More
Hypostasis meaning:
“Greek-speaking theologians of the early fourth century had three words for something that really exists, and exists in itself, as distinguished from an accident or a quality. The words are ousia, hypostasis, and hyparxis. … As the fourth century progressed, hypostasis became, more and more, the one term that was the center of controversy” (Lienhard).
Origen’s Influence
“The great majority of the Eastern clergy (at Nicaea) were ultimately disciples of Origen” (Frend, WHC: The Rise of Christianity). Since almost all delegates at Nicaea were from the East, this means that the great majority of the delegates at Nicaea followed Origen.
Three Hypostases
“Origen does consider the Son to be a distinct being dependent on the Father for his existence” (Ayres, p. 23).
“He taught that there were three hypostases within the Godhead” (Hanson, p. 184).
|
Origen rejected the idea from Logos theology that the Son previously was an aspect of God and said that the Son has always existed as a distinct Person.
He presented “the Son’s generation as an intimate expression of the Father’s existence.” “The Son has no origin except the Father.” “The Son may not share the ousia of the Father, but the Son is constantly in the Father.” Show More
“On a number of occasions Origen deploys the idea that the Son is generated ‘as the will from the mind’. This language serves not only to present the generation as non-material, but also to emphasize the Son’s generation as an intimate expression of the Father’s existence. Origen’s understanding that the Son has no origin except the Father, including no origin in time, also emphasizes that the Son’s existence is constituted by his imaging God from eternity. The Son may not share the ousia of the Father, but the Son is constantly in the Father” (Ayres, p. 27).
(For more details on Origen, see here.) |
Sabellianism
Origen opposed the teachings of Sabellius, who was active during the first decades of the third century. Like the Monarchians, the Sabellians were Monotheists, teaching that the Father and Son are a single Person. However, while the Monarchians made no distinction between the Father and the Son, to address the objection that the Bible presents the Son as a distinct Person, Sabellius proposed that the Father, Son, and Spirit are three distinct forms, aspects, or portions of the one divine Person. Sabellius also claimed that the Son is homoousios with the Father. However, Sabellius was deposed in 220, and his follower Paul of Samosata was deposed in 268, at a council that also condemned the term homoousios. Show More
One Person
Sabellius believed “there is but one undivided person in God” (Von Mosheim).
Hanson describes Sabellianism as “a failure to distinguish Father and Son” (Hanson, p. 224).
“He (Origen) deplores those heretics who confuse the ‘concepts’ of Father and Son and make them out to be one in hupostasis, as if the distinction between Father and Son were only a matter of concepts and of names, a purely mental distinction” (Williams, Rowan, p. 132).
Three aspects
“While he (Sabellius) maintained that there was but one person in God, he yet held that there are three forms, or aspects of the one God. Divers forms of one and the same being involve some real distinction” (page 218).
Homoousios
“If we can trust Basil [of Caesarea] here, it is interesting to observe that Sabellius had apparently used homoousios in a Trinitarian context early in the third century” (Hanson, p. 192).
See here for more details on Sabellius. |
Rome vs Alexandria c. 260
This dispute between the theologies of Sabellian and Origen is illustrated by the conflict between Rome and Alexandria around the year 260. Like Sabellius, Rome believed in only one divine Person and defended homoousios. Alexandria rejected homoousios and maintained that the Father and Son are two distinct divine Beings. Rome had the upper hand in this dispute because it was able to compel Alexandria to accept the term homoousios. However, Alexandria accepted it as meaning two substances of the same type, rather than as meaning one substance. Show More
Alexandria
“It seems … likely that Dionysius of Alexandria, in a campaign against some local Sabellians, had denied the term (homoousios)” (Ayres, p. 94).
“Those who complained of his (the bishop of Alexandria) erroneous doctrines to the bishop of Rome … particularly disliked his doctrine of the existence of three hypostases” (Hanson, 75).
Rome
“Dionysius of Rome … found homoousios acceptable but could not tolerate a division of the Godhead into three hypostases” (Hanson, p. 192, quoting Loofs). (The names of both bishops were Dionysius!)
“Dionysius of Rome harshly condemned those who divided the Trinity into three distinct hypostases” (Beatrice).
“His (bishop of Rome) doctrine could only with difficulty be distinguished from that of Sabellius” (Hanson, p. 193).
See here for a further discussion of this dispute. |
Council of Antioch c. 268
The Council of Antioch in 268, which deposed the Sabellian Paul of Samosata for teaching a ‘one hypostasis’ view and condemned the term homoousios, implying that Paul used it, also reflects the dispute between Sabellius’ ‘one hypostasis’ theology and Origen’s three hypostases. Show More
“Paul of Samosata (was) deposed by a council in Antioch in 268/9” (Ayres, p. 76).
“In using the expression ‘of one substance’, Paul declared that Father and Son were a solitary unit;” “a primitive undifferentiated unity” (Williams, p. 159-160).
“The Council of Antioch of 268 … did repudiate the word homoousios” (Hanson, p. 694). |
East/West Divide
So, already in the third century, this Controversy was an East/West divide: While Rome in the West defended the ‘one hypostasis’ view and the term homoousios, these concepts were denounced in Antioch, an important city in Eastern Christianity at the time. Generally, while the West had a Monarchian tradition, the East followed Origen. Show More
“Westerners, especially Romans, are probably rightly said to have held on to the spirit of the monarchian theology of the late second and early third centuries” (Lienhard).
Hanson refers to the “traditional Monarchianism” of the “Western bishops” (Hanson, p. 272). |
Possible Predecessors
In chronological sequence, this section discusses the theologians proposed by scholars in the past as possible predecessors of Arius. Many names have been suggested, including Paul of Samosata, who was deposed in 268, and Origen, after the Church in later centuries had excommunicated Origen posthumously. Show More
“A very large number of names have been suggested as predecessors of Arius” (Hanson, p. 60).
“His enemies first associated him with Paul of Samosata and with Judaizing tendences in Christology; later on, after the reputation of Origen had been virtually ruined in the Church, Arius was regarded by some as an Origen redivivus. Some more modern scholars have been much preoccupied with the question of whether Antioch or Alexandria should be seen as his spiritual and intellectual home” (Williams, p. 116). |
Plato
Plato’s philosophy of time and the origin of the universe, in which he distinguishes between that which exists without cause and the universe as we perceive it, which had a beginning, still dominated in the fourth-century intellectual world and shaped what the most influential writers of that time said about creation. It influenced all theologians in Arius’ time. Show More
“Plato’s Timaeus served as the central text upon which discussions of the world’s origins focused, not only in late antiquity, but right up to the revival of Christian Aristotelianism in the thirteenth century. … There can be no doubt that for many of the most influential writers of the age, from Origen to Eusebius Pamphilus, the contemporary discussion of time and the universe shaped their conceptions of what could intelligibly be said of creation” (Williams, p. 181).
“Plato distinguishes between what exists without cause and, therefore, always exists and never comes into being, and the universe as we perceive it, which had a beginning, is not eternal, and never exists stably” (Williams, p. 181).
Furthermore, Plato argues that, since the cosmos is beautiful, it must be modeled upon what is higher and better. The Creator made something like himself, reflecting order and beauty. To establish this order, God created time. The heavenly bodies are made to measure and regulate time. In other words, so to speak, time did not always exist (Williams, p. 181-2). |
Philo of Alexandria
Philo (20 BC – 50 AD) was a Hellenistic Jewish philosopher who interpreted Jewish scripture in terms of Greek philosophy, similar to how the Logos-theologians of the second and third centuries interpreted the New Testament through Greek philosophy. Wolfson claimed that Arius followed Philo because both taught two Logoi, the creation of the one Logos ex nihilo, and the incomparability of the other Logos (God). However, Hanson and Williams reject this claim. Williams says that Philo mapped out the ground for the Alexandrian theological tradition to build on, and that Arius’s theology is firmly within that tradition. Show More
Wolfson said: “Arius was responsible for ‘a reversion to the original view of Philo’ on the Logos, after the aberrations of a modalism which deprived the Logos of real subsistence” (Williams, p. 117, quoting Wolfson).
“Wolfson … suggested that Philo may have been a former of Arius’ thought because he too taught two Logoi, and the creation of one of them ex nihilo, and the incomparability of God. But then, Wolfson was obsessed to an excessive degree with the influence of Philo on the fathers; Philo’s Logos-doctrine is confused and obscure; he does not make the same division between the Logos and God as did the Arians. We cannot claim Philo as an ancestor of Arius’ thought” (Hanson, p. 60).
The similarities between Philo and Arius “should not … mislead us into hastily concluding that Arius was an assiduous student of Philo. What all this shows is, rather, that Philo mapped out the ground for the Alexandrian theological tradition to build on, and that Arius’ theological problematic is firmly within that tradition” (Williams, p. 122-123). |
Gnostics
Gnosticism was also not the source of Arius’ theology. Arius repeatedly rejects the favourite Gnostic concept of the ‘issue’ of beings from God. Show More
“There are some resemblances to Gnostic doctrines in Arius’ thought. … But these resemblances are either too general or refer to terms used for different things in the two authors. Furthermore, Arius several times rejects the favourite Gnostic concept of the ‘issue’ … of beings, from God” (Hanson, p. 60). |
Clement of Alexandria
Clement (150-215) was bishop of Alexandria in the early third century. There are numerous parallels between Arius and Clement. They shared a common ethos, but Clement differed in some key respects from Arius. For example:
Both Clement and Arius taught “two Logoi,” meaning that the Son or Logos is not an aspect of the Father but something in addition to the Father. However, Clement’s “two Logoi are quite different from those of Arius” (Hanson, p. 60).
While Arius taught ‘there was when He (the Son) was not, Clement taught “the eternity of the Son” (Hanson, p. 60). Show More
After showing that Clement’s theology is significantly different from that of Arius, Williams concludes:
“However, this is not to deny that Clement also passes on a positive legacy to Arius and his generation. … There are the numerous parallels in vocabulary between Arius’ Thalia and the language of Clement” (Williams, p. 126).
“It is less a question of a direct influence on Arius than of a common ethos … Arius begins from the apophatic tradition shared by Philo, Clement and heterodox Gnosticism … but his importance lies in his refusal to qualify these descriptions by the admission into the divine substance of a second principle, with its implications of a continuous scala naturae from the world to God” (Williams, p. 131).
|
Origen of Alexandria
Some saw Origen (185-253) as the ultimate source of Arius’ heresy. There were many similarities. Like Arius, Origen denied the Nicene teaching that the Son is from the Father’s substance and that He is homoousios (of the same substance) as the Father. Both also believed that only the Father exists without cause and that the Son:
-
-
- Is a distinct Person with a distinct mind,
- Was produced by the Father’s will, in contrast to Nicene theology, in which the Son exists essentially, not by the Father’s will,
- Is a created divine Being, using the term ‘created’ for any being who does not exist without cause,
- Is subordinate to the Father, and
- Does not know the Father fully.
However, there are also substantial differences between Origen and Arius. Origen emphasized the unity of the Father and Son much more than Arius did. While Arius presented the Father and Son as two distinct and independent divine Beings, Origen regarded them as one, not literally or in terms of substance, but from our perspective. In other words, Origen had a much higher view of the Son than Arius. Show More
“From very early on, there were those who saw Origen as the ultimate source of Arius’ heresy” (Williams, p. 131).
“Arius probably inherited some terms and even some ideas from Origen, … he certainly did not adopt any large or significant part of Origen’s theology” (Hanson, p. 70).
Arius “was not without influence from Origen, but cannot seriously be called an Origenist” (Hanson, p. 98).
See here for a further discussion of the similarities and differences between Origen and Arius. |
Dionysius of Alexandria
Dionysius was the bishop from 247 to 264 (Hanson, p. 72). Arius was probably born while he was the bishop of the city. The Arians claimed him as a great authority who supported their doctrine. Like Arius, in his view, the Son:
-
-
- Is a creature,
- Not of the same substance (homoousios) as the Father, and
- Did not exist before he came into existence.
For these reasons, it is impossible to avoid seeing a significant influence from Dionysius on Arius. If Arius had formulated his theology from various authors before his time, Dionysius would have contributed to it. Show More
“The Arians … were adducing (offering) Dionysius of Alexandria as a great authority in the past who supported their doctrine” (Hanson, p. 73). For example:
“The Son of God is a creature and generate, and he is not by nature belonging to but is alien in ousia from the Father, just as the planter of the vine is to the vine, and the shipbuilder to the ship; Further, because he is a creature he did not exist before he came into existence” (Hanson, p. 73. quoting Dionysius).
“Dionysius … rejected homoousios because it did not occur in the Bible” (Hanson, p. 75).
“However Dionysius may have refined his later theology, it is impossible to avoid seeing some influence from his work in the theology of Arius. The later Arians and Basil were right. The damning passage quoted from his letter … is altogether too like the doctrine of Arius for us to regard it as insignificant” (Hanson, p. 75-76). |
Paul of Samosata
Paul was bishop of Antioch from 260 to 268. Many scholars have proposed that Paul influenced Arius. However, Paul believed that the Son did not exist before Jesus’ human birth, and that Jesus is a mere man, though maximally inspired, an idea which Arius strongly opposed. Arius claimed that the Son existed before time began. Show More
“Many scholars have conjectured that the views of Paul of Samosata, or at least of his school, must have influenced Arius” (Hanson, p. 70).
Jesus is a mere man.
“Apparently for Paul the Son was Jesus Christ the historical figure without any preexistent history at all. And the stock accusation made against Paul by all ancient writers who mention him from the ivth century onward was that he declared Jesus to be no more than a mere man” (Hanson, p. 71).
“Apart from his superiority to us in all things because of his miraculous generation, he is ‘equal to us’. Wisdom dwells in Jesus ‘as in a temple’: the prophets and Moses and “many lords’ (kings?) were indwelt by Wisdom, but Jesus has the fullest degree of participation in it” (Williams, pp. 159-160).
Arius strongly opposed this idea:
“This is an idea which all Arian writers after Arius (and, in my view, probably Arius himself) regularly rejected.” “Arius believed firmly in a pre-existent Son” (Hanson, p. 71).
“Arius … ranges himself with those who most strongly opposed Paul” (Williams, p. 161).
|
Theognostus of Alexandria
Theognostus wrote from 247 to 280. His views were in many respects the opposite of Arius’:
While Arius believed that the Son is a distinct Person, created out of nothing, Theognostus thought that the Son is an aspect of the Father, namely, the Father’s Logos, and that the Son is an issue from the Father.
Therefore, the Son’s ousia was from the Father’s substance. He explicitly rejected the view that the Son was created out of nothing.
While Arius proclaimed two Logoi, meaning the Son is one Logos and the Father also has His own Logos, Theognostus taught that only one Logos exists, namely, that the Son is the Father’s own and only Logos.
While Theognostus was a monotheist, Oigen, Dionysius, and Arius believed that the Son is a distinct divine Being.
Theonostus’ theology could have been a precursor of Nicene theology. Show More
“We cannot glean any satisfactory evidence that Theognostus was a predecessor of Arius” (Hanson, p. 79).
His view “echoes Arian concerns in insisting that the Father is not divided,” but he also had some quite un-Arian views, such as that the Son is an issue of the Father (Hanson, p. 78).
“The ousia of the Son … was (not) introduced from non-existence, but it was of the Father’s ousia” (Hanson, p. 77).
“Theognostus explicitly disowned the doctrine, which Arius certainly held, that the Son was created out of non-existence” (Hanson, p. 78).
While Arius taught “that there are two Logoi (one immanent in the Father and one a name given somewhat inaccurately to the Son), … Theognostus insisted that there was only one Logos” (Hanson, p. 79). |
Methodius of Olympia
Methodius (died c. 311), bishop, ecclesiastical author, and martyr, like Arius, taught that the Father alone exists without cause, that the Son is wholly subordinate to and dependent on the Father, that the Son is the first of all created things, and that God created all other things through the Son. In other words, his theology resembles that of Arius. Show More
He taught:
“God alone … is ingenerate [meaning, exists without a cause]; nothing else in the universe is so, certainly not, he implies, the Son” (Hanson, p. 83).
“God the Father is the ‘unoriginated origin’, God the Son the beginning after the beginning, the origin of everything else created” (Hanson, p. 83).
The Son is “the first of all created things” (Hanson, p. 83).
“God the Father creates by his will alone. God the Son is the ‘hand’ of the Father, orders and adorns what the Father has created out of nothing” (Hanson, p. 83).
“The Son … is wholly dependent on the Father” (Hanson, p. 83).
|
Lucian of Antioch
The authorities in this section are discussed in chronological sequence. Lucian is the last of them. He died as a martyr in 312, the year before the emperors legalized Christianity, and only 6 years before Arius and his bishop clashed.
Lucian taught that the Logos, at the Incarnation, assumed a body without a soul (mind). In this way, the Logos directly experienced the pain and death of the cross. This was a typical Arian teaching and requires the Logos to be a distinct divine Person. Show More
Body without a Soul (mind)
“There is one fact, and one fact only, which we can with any confidence accept as authentic about Lucian’s doctrine. … Lucian taught that the Saviour at the Incarnation assumed a body without a soul” (Hanson, p. 83).
“’Lucian and all the Lucianists’, he (Epiphanius) says, ‘deny that the Son of God took a soul [i.e., a human soul], ‘in order that, of course, they may attach human experiences directly to the Logos” (Hanson, p. 80).
|
Arius claimed to have followed Lucian, but we do not know what else Lucian taught. Show More
Lucian’s description
“Jerome ... describes Lucian thus: ‘A very learned man, a presbyter of the church of Antioch” (Hanson, p. 81).
Arius followed Lucian:
“Arius describes Eusebius of Nicomedia, to whom he is writing, as ‘a genuine fellow-disciple of Lucian’” (Hanson, p. 80), implying that Arius himself was a “disciple of Lucian.”
Philostorgius also described Eusebius of Nicomedia, one of Arius’ close friends, as “the _ disciple of Lucian the martyr” (Hanson, p. 81).
Epiphanius refers to “the Arians” as “the Lucianists” (Hanson, p. 80).
Dedication Creed
“According to Sozomen, the second creed of the Dedication Council on Antioch in 341 was said to be a confession of faith stemming from Lucian” (Williams, pp. 163-4; cf. Hanson, pp. 80-81).
Knowledge of God
“Philostorgius knew of a tradition that Arius and the Lucianists disagreed about the Son’s knowledge of the Father” (Williams, p. 165).
While Arius maintained “that God was incomprehensible … also to the only-begotten Son of God” (Williams, p. 165), “the Lucianists … were remembered to have held that God was fully known by the Son” (Williams, p. 165).
We do not know what else Lucian taught.
“We can be sure that Arius drew on the teachings of Lucian, but … we do not know what Lucian taught” (Hanson, p. 82, cf. 83). “Our witnesses to Lucian’s theology are fragmentary and uncertain in the extreme” (Williams, p. 163).
Probably followed Lucian.
“It is wholly unlikely that Arius was a vox clamantis in deserto [a lone voice calling in the desert]. He represents a school, probably the school of Lucian of Antioch, and the school was to some extent independent of him” (Hanson, p. 97).
|
Antioch or Alexandria?
Some modern scholars have asked whether Antioch or Alexandria should be seen as Arius’ spiritual and intellectual home. In a recent book on Arius, Williams concluded that Arius is unmistakably Alexandrian. We have no justification even for regarding him as an exegetical rebel. Show More
“Some … modern scholars have been much preoccupied with the question of whether Antioch or Alexandria should be seen as his spiritual and intellectual home” (Williams, p. 116).
Nevertheless, “Arius is an unmistakable Alexandrian in his apophaticism [knowledge of God]. … We have no real justification even for regarding him as a rebel in the matter of exegesis” (Williams, p. 156). “Arius inherits a dual concern that is very typically Alexandrian” (Williams, p. 176). |
Conclusions
Specific Doctrines
This section discusses specific doctrines that Arius might have received from his predecessors. It relies on both the discussion above and the article – Was Origen the ultimate source of Arius’ heresy?
Unbegotten – Origen, Dionysius, and Methodius said that the Father alone exists without a cause and, therefore, without a beginning.
A Divine Creature – Therefore, Origen, Dionysius, and Methodius also described the Son as a divine ‘creature,’ using the term ‘creature’ for any being who does not exist without cause, but whose existence was caused by another. Show More
“Origen did … describe the Son both as ‘having come into existence’ and as a ‘creature’. … But at the same time, he declares his belief in the eternity of the Son as a distinct entity from the Father” (Hanson, pp. 63-64). Origen described the Son as “the originated God” (Hanson, p. 62).
Dionysius described the Son of God as “a creature,” “alien in ousia from the Father” (Hanson, p. 73).
Methodius: The Son is “the first of all created things” (Hanson, p. 83). |
Subordinate – “Origen, with Arius, can be said to have subordinated the Son to the Father” (Hanson, p. 64). However, Hanson also explains that Origen had a much higher view of the Son that Arius had. Nevertheless, Hanson adds that all theologians of the first three centuries regarded the Son to be subordinate to the Father. Show More
“Subordinationism might indeed, until the denouement (end) of the controversy, have been described as accepted orthodoxy” (Hanson, p. xix).
“’Subordinationism’, it is true was pre-Nicene orthodoxy” [Henry Bettenson, The Early Christian Fathers p. 239].
“There is no theologian in the Eastern or the Western Church before the outbreak of the Arian Controversy [in the fourth century], who does not in some sense regard the Son as subordinate to the Father” (Hanson, p. 64). |
Knowledge of God – Like Arius, Origen taught that the Son does not fully understand the Father.
Produced by the Father’s will – In Nicene theology, since the Logos is an aspect of the Father, namely, His Wisdom (see here), the Logos exists essentially and not by the Father’s will. In contrast, several pre-Nicene authors agreed with Arius that “the Son was produced by the Father’s will.” Show More
“Ignatius, Justin, Hippolytus, Clement of Alexandria and Origen,” like Arius, taught “the Son was produced by the Father’s will” (Hanson, p. 90). |
Homoousios – Origen and Dionysius rejected the concept that the Son is homoousios (of the same substance) as the Father. Show More
Dionysius of Alexandria “rejected homoousios” (Hanson, p. 75), and Origen would not have accepted it (see here).
Dionysius claimed that “the Son of God … is alien in ousia from the Father” (Hanson, p. 73). |
Eternal – Dionysius of Alexandria said that the Son did not always exist. Show More
“Because he is a creature he did not exist before he came into existence” (Hanson, p. 73). |
Ex nihilo – However, nobody said, like Arius, that the Son was formed from nothing. That was probably a rebuttal of the Nicene view that the Son was begotten from the substance of the Father. Show More
Arius’ view, that “the Son was created from non-existent things, has never been supplied with a convincing antecedent” (Hanson, p. 88). |
Who did Arius follow?
Arius opposed Gnosticism and Paul of Samosata. He was also not a Logos-theologian:
“Our mistake is to try to interpret him (Arius) in terms of a theology with which he was not at home, the Logos-theology he shares with his opponents” (Williams, p. 12). |
Arius is unmistakably Alexandrian in his theology, and Plato, Philo, Clement, Origen, and Lucian shaped the general heritage of the church in Alexandria:
Arius’ theology was “clearly the result of a very large number of theological views” (Williams, p. 171). |
The two authors whom Arius could rightly claim as his theological ancestors are Dionysius of Alexandria and Methodius of Olympia. Dionysius likely contributed to Arius’ theology (Hanson, p. 76), and Methodius of Olympia regarded the Father alone as ingenerate; the ‘unoriginated origin’ and the Son as the first of the created things, wholly dependent on the Father (Hanson, p. 83).
While Hanson said that “Arius … represents a school, probably the school of Lucian of Antioch” (Hanson, p. 97), Williams proposed that “it is perhaps a mistake to look for one self-contained and exclusive ‘theological school’ to which to assign him” (Williams, p. 115).
Arius was a conservative.
In the traditional account of the Controversy, Arianism was first proposed by Arius, opposing an established orthodoxy. Therefore, Arius was the founder of Arianism. Show More
Britannica defines Arianism as “a heresy first proposed by Arius of Alexandria that affirmed that Christ is not divine but a created being.”
“Athanasius’ account begins by presenting Arius as the originator of a new heresy” (Ayres, p. 107).
In the past, many writers have assumed that “Arianism … had been from the outset an easily recognised heresy in contrast to a known and universally recognised orthodoxy” (Hanson, p. 95). |
However, in his recent book on Arius (Arius, Heresy & Tradition – 2002/1987), Rowan Williams described Arius not as a rebel but an Alexandrian conservative.
“A great deal of recent work seeking to understand Arian spirituality has, not surprisingly, helped to demolish the notion of Arius and his supporters as deliberate radicals, attacking a time-honoured tradition” (Williams, 21).
“Arius was a committed theological conservative; more specifically, a conservative Alexandrian” (Williams, 175). |
Arius did not say anything new. He merely selected and reorganized traditional ideas. Therefore, Arius can no longer be regarded as the strange monster of heresy that scholars of previous centuries depicted him as. Show More
Arius’ book (The Thalia) “is conservative in the sense that there is almost nothing in it that could not be found in earlier writers; it is radical and individual in the way it combines and reorganizes traditional ideas and presses them to their logical conclusions” (Williams, p. 177).
“Arius … can no longer be regarded as the strange monster of heresy which Gwatkin, and even Harnack, depicted him to be” (Hanson, pp. 84-85). |
Lewis Ayres identifies four trajectories at the beginning of the fourth century in his book on the Controversy (Nicaea and its legacy, An Approach to Fourth-Century Trinitarian Theology – 2004). None of the four is Arius’ theology. Instead, Ayres classifies Arius as one of the Eusebians, the trajectory that followed the two Eusebii. Show More
“My second theological trajectory is the one in which we locate Arius himself. This loose alliance I will term ‘Eusebian’. When I use this term I mean to designate any who would have found common ground with either of Arius’ most prominent supporters, Eusebius of Nicomedia or Eusebius of Caesarea” (Ayres, p. 52). |
In 1987, Lienhard wrote that Arius was just another member of the dyohypostatic tradition, meaning the group who believed that the Father and Son are two distinct hypostases (Persons). Show More
“Arius too, far from being an original thinker, was simply one more adherent of the dyohypostatic (two hypostases) tradition” (Lienhard). |
Arius did not cause the Controversy.
The analysis above shows that the authors preceding Arius had conflicting views about the nature of the Son. Since Arius did not develop a new theology, but was an Alexandrian conservative, contrary to the traditional account, he did not cause the Controversy. The 4th-century Controversy was not new but continued the 3rd-century controversy. Show More
“The views of Arius were such as in a peculiar manner to bring into unavoidable prominence a doctrinal crisis which had gradually been gathering … He was the spark that started the explosion, but in himself he was of no great significance” (Hanson, p. xvii-xviii).
“We will find pre-existing deep theological tensions at the beginning of the fourth century. Controversy over Arius was the spark that ignited a fire waiting to happen, and the origins of the dispute do not lie simply in the beliefs of one thinker, but in existing tensions that formed his background” (Ayres, p. 20).
“The conflict in the fourth century was one between two theological traditions, both of which were well established by the beginning of the century” (Lienhard). |
It was not an Arian Controversy.
It is traditional to believe that Arianism is equal to Arius’ theology. However, since Arius was a member of an existing theological trajectory, which Ayres refers to as the Eusebians (the followers of Eusebius), Arius was not the founder of Arianism:
The so-called Arians appealed to great names in the past, but never to Arius! On the contrary, they explicitly rejected some of his statements. See, for example, the Dedication Creed.
The people of his day, whether they agreed with him or not, did not regard his writings as worth preserving. He did not leave behind a school of disciples.
He had many supporters, not because they followed him, but because they were from the same theological trajectory and regarded Alexander’s theology as more dangerous.
Arius’ dispute with his bishop was the spark that ignited the Controversy, but Arius himself was not of any great significance.
Therefore, the term ‘Arian’ is a serious misnomer. The conflict of the fourth century was not about Arius’ theology. Show More
The Controversy was not about Arius:
“We have no knowledge of later Arian use of the Thalia [Arius’ book] … which suggests that it was not to the fore in the debates of the mid-century” (Williams, p. 65).
He was not important.
“The people of his (Arius’) day, whether they agreed with him or not, did not regard him as a particularly significant writer. … Neither his supporters nor his opponents thought them (his writings) worth preserving. … He virtually disappears from the controversy at an early stage in its course” (Hanson, xvii).
“The Arians could and did appeal to great names in the past … but not Arius” (Hanson, p. 828)!
He did not leave a school of followers.
“Arius evidently made converts to his views … but he left no school of disciples” (Williams, p. 233).
Eusebius of Caesarea “thought the theology of Alexander a greater menace than that of Arius” (Williams, 173).
“Many of Arius’ earliest supporters appear to have rallied to him because they, like him, opposed Alexander’s theology” (Ayres, p. 14).
See here for a further discussion. |
One vs Two Logoi
Some, like Philo and Clement of Alexandria, spoke about two Logoi. Others, like Theognostus of Alexandria, “insisted that there was only one Logos” (Hanson, p. 79):
One Logos – To say that only one Logos exists means that the Son is the Father’s own and only Logos, which further means that the Son is part of or an aspect of the Father. This is what Nicene theology proclaimed. Specifically, Nicene theology taught that the Son is the Father’s own and only Wisdom or Logos. Therefore, in Nicene theology, the Father and Son are a single Person (hypostasis). Show More
Nicene theology:
“There is no need to postulate two Logoi” (Hanson, p. 431, quoting Athanasius).
“In Alexander, and in Athanasius … Christ is the one power and wisdom of the Father” (Ayres, p. 54).
“Alexander taught that … as the Father’s Word and Wisdom the Son must always have been with the Father” (Ayres, p. 16).
See here for a discussion of Nicene theology. |
Two Logoi – To say two Logoi exist means that the Son is not the Father’s only Logos, but that an additional Logos was brought into being when the Son was begotten. That was the Arian view. Show More
“Arius also talks of two wisdoms and powers, speaking of a Logos that was not distinct from the Father’s hypostasis, after whom the Son is designated Word” (Ayres, p. 55).
“There are … two Wisdoms, one God’s own who has existed eternally with God, the other the Son who was brought into existence. … There is another Word in God besides the Son” (Hanson, p. 13, cf. 16, Athanasius’ paraphrasing of Arius’ teaching). |
The Core Issue
Created/Divine – Many think the core issue was whether the Son is a created being or divine. No, the Arians did believe that the Son is divine. For them, He was a created divine being. They called Him theos, which is often translated as “God.” Show More
“Christ is our God by whom we were made. He can and should be called ‘God’ and be adored, glorified and honoured. So God has produced a God, the Creator a Creator, but there is still a difference between them. God the Father is the God of God the Son who can be called secundus Deus (second God)” (Hanson, p. 103, quoting from Gryson’s summary of the Arian theology “from the Arian scholia on the MS of the Council of Aquileia” (Hanson, p. 102). |
Subordinate – Some think the core issue was whether the Son is subordinate to the Father. That was also not the core issue, for the Nicenes also described the Son as subordinate to the Father. Show More
Alexander did regard the Son as subordinate to the Father because “he argues for a ‘great distance’ between the unbegotten Father and the created order, and then describes the nature (φύσις) of the only-begotten Word as mediating between these two, ‘holding the middle place’ (μεσιτεύουσα)” (Ayres, p. 44).
“The initial debate (i.e., between Arius and Alexander) was not about the rightness or wrongness of hierarchical models of the Trinity, which were common to both sides” (Williams, 109).
“In all the previous discussions (before Basil of Caesarea) of the term (homoousios) … a certain ontological subordination is at least implied. One can even point to Athanasius’ pointed lack of willingness to use homoousios of the Father’s relationship to the Son and his consistent picture of the Son as proper to the Father, as the Father’s own wisdom” (Ayres, p. 206).
This concept of “proper to the Father” is important. It comes from the Greek term idios and, as used by Athanasius, means that the Son is an aspect of the Father.
“All important scholars since Petavius admit subordination in the Nicene doctrine of the Trinity” (Philip Schaff, History of the Christian Church, Vol. III (311–600) (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1950) 683). |
Homoousios – Many think the core issue was whether the Son is homoousios with the Father. That was also not the core issue. One indication is that the term fell out of the Controversy soon after Nicaea and was only brought back into the Controversy in the 350s, 30 years after Nicaea. Show More
“After Nicaea homoousios is not mentioned again in truly contemporary sources for two decades. … It was not seen as that useful or important” (Ayres, 96).
“Athanasius’ decision to make Nicaea and homoousios central to his theology has its origins in the shifting climate of the 350s” (Ayres, p. 144).
“He (Athanasius) began to use it first in the De Deeretis … in 356 or 357” (Hanson, p. 438). |
Furthermore, Athanasius’ explanation of the term was similar to that of Eusebius, the leader of the so-called Arians. Both interpreted the term highly figuratively, simply as meaning that the Son came forth from the being of the Father, although they had very different understandings of what that means. Show More
“Athanasius seems not only to allude to, but also to build on, the argument of Eusebius of Caesarea in his Letter to his Diocese written in 326. … Athanasius actually directly draws on the basic structure of Eusebius’ account of how homoousios is only intended to emphasize that the Son is ‘from God’” (Ayres, p. 143).. |
One or two Logoi – The core issue in the Arian Controversy was this distinction between one or two Logoi, or between one or two hypostases. In other words, the core issue was whether the Son is a distinct divine Person with a distinct mind.
One Logos – If only one Logos exists, as claimed by the Monotheists, including the Modalists, Sabellians, and the Nicenes, with Athanasius as the prime example, it follows that the Father and Son are a single hypostasis (Person):
As stated, in Nicene theology, the Son is a feature or aspect of the Father. Therefore, only one divine Person exists. Show More
Alexander – “[Rowan] Williams’ work is most illuminating. Alexander of Alexandria, Williams thinks, had maintained that the Son … is a property or quality of the Father, impersonal and belonging to his substance” (Hanson, p. 92).
Athanasius – “Athanasius’ gut reaction is that there can be only one eternal reality and source, and that proposing more than one hypostasis would imply a dualism” (Ayres, p. 48).
Athanasius – “He clearly approves of the sentence of Dionysius of Rome that it is wrong to divide the divine monarchy into ‘three powers and separate hypostases and three Godheads’, thereby postulating ‘three diverse hypostases wholly separated from each other’” (Hanson, p. 445). |
The two main Nicene creeds of the 4th century, the Nicene Creed and the Manifesto at Serdica, explicitly declared that the Father and Son are a single hypostasis. Show More
Nicene Creed – “The production of N [the Nicene Creed] … must have been deeply disturbing for many who could not seriously be described as Arian in sympathy but could not believe that God had only one hypostasis, as the creed apparently professed” (Hanson, p. 274).
Serdica – “We have received and have been taught this … tradition: that there is one hypostasis, which the heretics (also) call ousia, of the Father and of the Son and of the Holy Spirit” (Hanson, p. 301). (See here for a discussion of this manifesto.).
|
If the Father and Son are a single Person, then it further follows that the Son has the same substance as the Father and is, like the Father, eternal, immutable, and impassible.
Concerning the incarnation, in Nicene theology, since the Logos is immutable and impassible, He cannot become a human being. Rather, Jesus Christ is a human being with a human mind, inspired by God’s Word through the Holy Spirit (see here).
Two Logoi – If two Logoi exist, as Origen and the Arians believed, then the Father and Son are two distinct hypostases (two Persons). It follows that the Father alone exists without a cause, that the Son did not always exist but is a divine creature, produced by the Father’s will, and that the Son is subordinate to the Father. With respect to the incarnation, the Arians believed that Jesus Christ did not have a human mind. Rather, Jesus Christ is the eternal Logos in a human body. Show More
“Arius saw the Son as a being distinct from … the Father” (Ayres, p. 16).
“We have to resist the anachronistic characterization of him (Arius) as an antitrinitarian theologian.” “He writes simply, ‘So there are three hypostaseis,’” meaning “the set of beings that form the object (or objects) of Christian confession. … the three hypostaseis seemingly form a certain unity” (Anatolios, pp. 47-48). |
See here for a discussion of the core issue in the Controversy. That article identifies the core issue by analysing the various phases of the Controversy and by showing who opposed whom.
Did Athanasius accept three hypostases?
It is sometimes said that Athanasius accepted three hypostases in 362, but that requires qualification. A hypostasis is something that exists distinctly from other things. Athanasius wrote that ‘three hypostases’ would be acceptable if the phrase is used figuratively and not literally. To quote him, he stated that the phrase is acceptable if it does not mean that “each hypostasis was divided apart by itself” but only if the Son and Spirit are “inseparable from the ousia of … the Father.” Show More
“We made enquiry of them whether they meant, like the Arian madmen, hypostases foreign and strange, and alien in essence from one another, and that each hypostasis was divided apart by itself” (Ayres, p. 174).
Athanasius declared that ‘three hypostases’ are acceptable if it means “Father, Son and Spirit each subsisting distinctly … a single Godhead and a single ultimate principle and a Son consubstantial with the Father … and the Holy Spirit, neither a creature nor an alien, but belonging to and inseparable from the ousia of the Son and of the Father” (Ayres, p. 174).
Athanasius wrote this letter seeking the support of the Homoiousians (whom some called the semi-Arians), but after 362, he continued to prefer one hypostasis. He did not change his theology. |
The Arian Controversy is made to sound very complex, but it is really simple.
The Nicene believed that the Father and Son are a single Person with a single mind. The benefit of the Nicene view is that it retained Biblical monotheism. A disadvantage of the Nicene view is that the Son of God did not suffer or die. Contrary to the New Testament, a mere man suffered and died.
The ‘Arians’ believed that the Father and Son are two distinct Persons with distinct minds. The question for Protestants is, does the Bible present the Son as a distinct Being?
Variations within the main trajectories.
There were, of course, many variations within the two main categories.
The dyohopostatic (Eusebian) tradition divided into various views, such as the Homoians, Homoiousians, and Heterousians.
Monotheism also took different forms:
In Modalism (Monarchianism), the Son has no distinct existence.
In Sabellianism, the Son (the Logos) and the Spirit are distinct features of the Father, but they have only temporary existence.
In Nicene theology, the Son and Spirit are distinct aspects of the Father that exist eternally.
None of these views is exactly the same as the modern Trinity doctrine. Theology evolved during the 4th century and beyond.
Show More
“Original Nicene theology was a fluid and diverse phenomenon, and one that kept evolving.” “It was to be many years before … (it) evolved into what I shall term pro-Nicene theology” (Ayres, p. 99).
“This is not the story of a defence of orthodoxy, but of a search for orthodoxy” (Hanson, xix-xx). |
Other Articles